Loading…

Originalism: Standard and procedure

Originalism is often promoted as a better way of getting constitutional answers. That claim leads to disappointment when the answers prove hard to find. To borrow a distinction from philosophy, originalism is better understood as a standard, not a decision procedure. It offers an account of what mak...

Full description

Saved in:
Bibliographic Details
Published in:Harvard law review 2022-01, Vol.135 (3), p.777-830
Main Author: Sachs, Stephen E
Format: Article
Language:English
Subjects:
Online Access:Get full text
Tags: Add Tag
No Tags, Be the first to tag this record!
cited_by
cites
container_end_page 830
container_issue 3
container_start_page 777
container_title Harvard law review
container_volume 135
creator Sachs, Stephen E
description Originalism is often promoted as a better way of getting constitutional answers. That claim leads to disappointment when the answers prove hard to find. To borrow a distinction from philosophy, originalism is better understood as a standard, not a decision procedure. It offers an account of what makes right constitutional answers right. What it doesn't offer, and shouldn't be blamed for failing to offer, is a step-by-step procedure for finding them. Distinguishing standards from decision procedures explains originalism's tolerance for uncertainty about history or its application; justifies the creation of certain kinds of judicial doctrines (though not others); clarifies longstanding battles over interpretation and construction; identifies both limits and strengths for the theory's normative defenders; and gives us a better picture of originalism's use in practice. It would be nice if the correct constitutional theory also gave us easy answers in contested cases. But you can't have everything. Knowing the right standard might not lead us to those answers, but it still might be worth knowing all the same.
format article
fullrecord <record><control><sourceid>gale_proqu</sourceid><recordid>TN_cdi_gale_businessinsightsgauss_A690097706</recordid><sourceformat>XML</sourceformat><sourcesystem>PC</sourcesystem><galeid>A690097706</galeid><informt_id>10.3316/agispt.20220201061289</informt_id><sourcerecordid>A690097706</sourcerecordid><originalsourceid>FETCH-LOGICAL-g2699-6592b40e2ec2a6c9809fa3a82169c21142a0e0658088a6f6e6cf0dcc96677f703</originalsourceid><addsrcrecordid>eNptz9tKAzEQBuAgCtbqOxR6JbgyyW5z8K4UtYVCL1ToXUiz2TRlDzXJgo9vaBUtlIQMDN8kfy7QgGCKM8Ho-hINADDLOMbra3QTwg4AaM6KARqvvLOuVbULzdPoLaq2VL4cpTLa-06bsvfmFl1Vqg7m7qcO0cfL8_tsni1Xr4vZdJlZQoXI6ESQTQGGGE0U1YKDqFSueIohNMG4IAoM0AkHzhWtqKG6glJrQSljFYN8iMbHe9PLn70JUe663qdsQRJKCsEZE-JPWVUb6dqqi17pxgUtp1QACMbS34YoO6OsaY1XddeayqX2iX8849MqTeP02YH7k4FkovmKVvUhyMV8cWof_tlNH1xrQjqCs9sYjiMnfH7kvnFRKuvCPspglNfbQ7JDu_NWlp2TGGSeY_rLCJC0AQPFhIv8G8PBm2I</addsrcrecordid><sourcetype>Aggregation Database</sourcetype><iscdi>true</iscdi><recordtype>article</recordtype><pqid>2624987799</pqid></control><display><type>article</type><title>Originalism: Standard and procedure</title><source>International Bibliography of the Social Sciences (IBSS)</source><source>Nexis UK</source><source>Business Source Ultimate【Trial: -2024/12/31】【Remote access available】</source><source>PAIS Index</source><source>Worldwide Political Science Abstracts</source><creator>Sachs, Stephen E</creator><creatorcontrib>Sachs, Stephen E</creatorcontrib><description>Originalism is often promoted as a better way of getting constitutional answers. That claim leads to disappointment when the answers prove hard to find. To borrow a distinction from philosophy, originalism is better understood as a standard, not a decision procedure. It offers an account of what makes right constitutional answers right. What it doesn't offer, and shouldn't be blamed for failing to offer, is a step-by-step procedure for finding them. Distinguishing standards from decision procedures explains originalism's tolerance for uncertainty about history or its application; justifies the creation of certain kinds of judicial doctrines (though not others); clarifies longstanding battles over interpretation and construction; identifies both limits and strengths for the theory's normative defenders; and gives us a better picture of originalism's use in practice. It would be nice if the correct constitutional theory also gave us easy answers in contested cases. But you can't have everything. Knowing the right standard might not lead us to those answers, but it still might be worth knowing all the same.</description><identifier>ISSN: 0017-811X</identifier><identifier>EISSN: 2161-976X</identifier><language>eng</language><publisher>Cambridge: Harvard Law Review Association</publisher><subject>Analysis ; Conservatism ; Constitutional history ; Decision making ; Judges &amp; magistrates ; Management ; Originality ; Political aspects ; Political philosophy ; Procedure (Law) ; Toleration ; Uncertainty</subject><ispartof>Harvard law review, 2022-01, Vol.135 (3), p.777-830</ispartof><rights>COPYRIGHT 2022 Harvard Law Review Association</rights><rights>Copyright Harvard Law Review Association Jan 2022</rights><lds50>peer_reviewed</lds50><woscitedreferencessubscribed>false</woscitedreferencessubscribed></display><links><openurl>$$Topenurl_article</openurl><openurlfulltext>$$Topenurlfull_article</openurlfulltext><thumbnail>$$Tsyndetics_thumb_exl</thumbnail><link.rule.ids>314,780,784,27866,33223</link.rule.ids></links><search><creatorcontrib>Sachs, Stephen E</creatorcontrib><title>Originalism: Standard and procedure</title><title>Harvard law review</title><description>Originalism is often promoted as a better way of getting constitutional answers. That claim leads to disappointment when the answers prove hard to find. To borrow a distinction from philosophy, originalism is better understood as a standard, not a decision procedure. It offers an account of what makes right constitutional answers right. What it doesn't offer, and shouldn't be blamed for failing to offer, is a step-by-step procedure for finding them. Distinguishing standards from decision procedures explains originalism's tolerance for uncertainty about history or its application; justifies the creation of certain kinds of judicial doctrines (though not others); clarifies longstanding battles over interpretation and construction; identifies both limits and strengths for the theory's normative defenders; and gives us a better picture of originalism's use in practice. It would be nice if the correct constitutional theory also gave us easy answers in contested cases. But you can't have everything. Knowing the right standard might not lead us to those answers, but it still might be worth knowing all the same.</description><subject>Analysis</subject><subject>Conservatism</subject><subject>Constitutional history</subject><subject>Decision making</subject><subject>Judges &amp; magistrates</subject><subject>Management</subject><subject>Originality</subject><subject>Political aspects</subject><subject>Political philosophy</subject><subject>Procedure (Law)</subject><subject>Toleration</subject><subject>Uncertainty</subject><issn>0017-811X</issn><issn>2161-976X</issn><fulltext>true</fulltext><rsrctype>article</rsrctype><creationdate>2022</creationdate><recordtype>article</recordtype><sourceid>7TQ</sourceid><sourceid>7UB</sourceid><sourceid>8BJ</sourceid><recordid>eNptz9tKAzEQBuAgCtbqOxR6JbgyyW5z8K4UtYVCL1ToXUiz2TRlDzXJgo9vaBUtlIQMDN8kfy7QgGCKM8Ho-hINADDLOMbra3QTwg4AaM6KARqvvLOuVbULzdPoLaq2VL4cpTLa-06bsvfmFl1Vqg7m7qcO0cfL8_tsni1Xr4vZdJlZQoXI6ESQTQGGGE0U1YKDqFSueIohNMG4IAoM0AkHzhWtqKG6glJrQSljFYN8iMbHe9PLn70JUe663qdsQRJKCsEZE-JPWVUb6dqqi17pxgUtp1QACMbS34YoO6OsaY1XddeayqX2iX8849MqTeP02YH7k4FkovmKVvUhyMV8cWof_tlNH1xrQjqCs9sYjiMnfH7kvnFRKuvCPspglNfbQ7JDu_NWlp2TGGSeY_rLCJC0AQPFhIv8G8PBm2I</recordid><startdate>20220101</startdate><enddate>20220101</enddate><creator>Sachs, Stephen E</creator><general>Harvard Law Review Association</general><scope>N95</scope><scope>XI7</scope><scope>IHI</scope><scope>ILT</scope><scope>7TQ</scope><scope>7UB</scope><scope>8BJ</scope><scope>DHY</scope><scope>DON</scope><scope>FQK</scope><scope>JBE</scope></search><sort><creationdate>20220101</creationdate><title>Originalism: Standard and procedure</title><author>Sachs, Stephen E</author></sort><facets><frbrtype>5</frbrtype><frbrgroupid>cdi_FETCH-LOGICAL-g2699-6592b40e2ec2a6c9809fa3a82169c21142a0e0658088a6f6e6cf0dcc96677f703</frbrgroupid><rsrctype>articles</rsrctype><prefilter>articles</prefilter><language>eng</language><creationdate>2022</creationdate><topic>Analysis</topic><topic>Conservatism</topic><topic>Constitutional history</topic><topic>Decision making</topic><topic>Judges &amp; magistrates</topic><topic>Management</topic><topic>Originality</topic><topic>Political aspects</topic><topic>Political philosophy</topic><topic>Procedure (Law)</topic><topic>Toleration</topic><topic>Uncertainty</topic><toplevel>peer_reviewed</toplevel><toplevel>online_resources</toplevel><creatorcontrib>Sachs, Stephen E</creatorcontrib><collection>Gale_Business Insights: Global</collection><collection>Business Insights: Essentials</collection><collection>Gale In Context: U.S. History</collection><collection>LegalTrac</collection><collection>PAIS Index</collection><collection>Worldwide Political Science Abstracts</collection><collection>International Bibliography of the Social Sciences (IBSS)</collection><collection>PAIS International</collection><collection>PAIS International (Ovid)</collection><collection>International Bibliography of the Social Sciences</collection><collection>International Bibliography of the Social Sciences</collection><jtitle>Harvard law review</jtitle></facets><delivery><delcategory>Remote Search Resource</delcategory><fulltext>fulltext</fulltext></delivery><addata><au>Sachs, Stephen E</au><format>journal</format><genre>article</genre><ristype>JOUR</ristype><atitle>Originalism: Standard and procedure</atitle><jtitle>Harvard law review</jtitle><date>2022-01-01</date><risdate>2022</risdate><volume>135</volume><issue>3</issue><spage>777</spage><epage>830</epage><pages>777-830</pages><issn>0017-811X</issn><eissn>2161-976X</eissn><abstract>Originalism is often promoted as a better way of getting constitutional answers. That claim leads to disappointment when the answers prove hard to find. To borrow a distinction from philosophy, originalism is better understood as a standard, not a decision procedure. It offers an account of what makes right constitutional answers right. What it doesn't offer, and shouldn't be blamed for failing to offer, is a step-by-step procedure for finding them. Distinguishing standards from decision procedures explains originalism's tolerance for uncertainty about history or its application; justifies the creation of certain kinds of judicial doctrines (though not others); clarifies longstanding battles over interpretation and construction; identifies both limits and strengths for the theory's normative defenders; and gives us a better picture of originalism's use in practice. It would be nice if the correct constitutional theory also gave us easy answers in contested cases. But you can't have everything. Knowing the right standard might not lead us to those answers, but it still might be worth knowing all the same.</abstract><cop>Cambridge</cop><pub>Harvard Law Review Association</pub><tpages>54</tpages></addata></record>
fulltext fulltext
identifier ISSN: 0017-811X
ispartof Harvard law review, 2022-01, Vol.135 (3), p.777-830
issn 0017-811X
2161-976X
language eng
recordid cdi_gale_businessinsightsgauss_A690097706
source International Bibliography of the Social Sciences (IBSS); Nexis UK; Business Source Ultimate【Trial: -2024/12/31】【Remote access available】; PAIS Index; Worldwide Political Science Abstracts
subjects Analysis
Conservatism
Constitutional history
Decision making
Judges & magistrates
Management
Originality
Political aspects
Political philosophy
Procedure (Law)
Toleration
Uncertainty
title Originalism: Standard and procedure
url http://sfxeu10.hosted.exlibrisgroup.com/loughborough?ctx_ver=Z39.88-2004&ctx_enc=info:ofi/enc:UTF-8&ctx_tim=2025-01-07T13%3A15%3A58IST&url_ver=Z39.88-2004&url_ctx_fmt=infofi/fmt:kev:mtx:ctx&rfr_id=info:sid/primo.exlibrisgroup.com:primo3-Article-gale_proqu&rft_val_fmt=info:ofi/fmt:kev:mtx:journal&rft.genre=article&rft.atitle=Originalism:%20Standard%20and%20procedure&rft.jtitle=Harvard%20law%20review&rft.au=Sachs,%20Stephen%20E&rft.date=2022-01-01&rft.volume=135&rft.issue=3&rft.spage=777&rft.epage=830&rft.pages=777-830&rft.issn=0017-811X&rft.eissn=2161-976X&rft_id=info:doi/&rft_dat=%3Cgale_proqu%3EA690097706%3C/gale_proqu%3E%3Cgrp_id%3Ecdi_FETCH-LOGICAL-g2699-6592b40e2ec2a6c9809fa3a82169c21142a0e0658088a6f6e6cf0dcc96677f703%3C/grp_id%3E%3Coa%3E%3C/oa%3E%3Curl%3E%3C/url%3E&rft_id=info:oai/&rft_pqid=2624987799&rft_id=info:pmid/&rft_galeid=A690097706&rft_informt_id=10.3316/agispt.20220201061289&rfr_iscdi=true