Loading…
Aristotle on the Period (Rhet. 3. 9)
Aristotle (Rhet. 3.9) distinguishes two types of style, the ‘periodic’ or ‘rounded’ (λ⋯ξιςκατεστραμμέη) and the ‘non-periodic’, ‘strung-on’ or ‘continuous’ (λέξιςε;ἰρομένη).* The latter is typical of prose in its young and unsophisticated state, and Aristotle is not much interested in it; his discus...
Saved in:
Published in: | Classical quarterly 1982-01, Vol.32 (1), p.89-99 |
---|---|
Main Author: | |
Format: | Article |
Language: | English |
Subjects: | |
Citations: | Items that cite this one |
Online Access: | Get full text |
Tags: |
Add Tag
No Tags, Be the first to tag this record!
|
cited_by | cdi_FETCH-LOGICAL-c375t-cb002a4e94244997c85594ede8855278845a7a832a8938d539d357b220d39a313 |
---|---|
cites | |
container_end_page | 99 |
container_issue | 1 |
container_start_page | 89 |
container_title | Classical quarterly |
container_volume | 32 |
creator | Fowler, R. L. |
description | Aristotle (Rhet. 3.9) distinguishes two types of style, the ‘periodic’ or ‘rounded’ (λ⋯ξιςκατεστραμμέη) and the ‘non-periodic’, ‘strung-on’ or ‘continuous’ (λέξιςε;ἰρομένη).* The latter is typical of prose in its young and unsophisticated state, and Aristotle is not much interested in it; his discussion of the periodic style is much longer, with subdivisions being introduced and numerous examples given. His basic definition of the period is not, however, clear, and the point has seen some controversy. There are two possibilities. (1) He defines the period ‘rhythmically’ (as I shall call it). The essential feature of the period is that its beginning and end are marked off by specific metrical rhythms (discussed in the preceding chapter, 3.8, where Aristotle recommends the paean).1 (2) He defines it ‘logically’. The period is a syntactic structure with an inner cohesion produced by the logical, pre-planned arrangement of its parts according to the requirements of the whole.2 The current consensus at least of written opinions is that Aristotle intended the first;3 I believe that the issue can be settled fairly decisively in favour of the second. |
doi_str_mv | 10.1017/S0009838800022837 |
format | article |
fullrecord | <record><control><sourceid>jstor_proqu</sourceid><recordid>TN_cdi_proquest_journals_1294576148</recordid><sourceformat>XML</sourceformat><sourcesystem>PC</sourcesystem><cupid>10_1017_S0009838800022837</cupid><jstor_id>638741</jstor_id><sourcerecordid>638741</sourcerecordid><originalsourceid>FETCH-LOGICAL-c375t-cb002a4e94244997c85594ede8855278845a7a832a8938d539d357b220d39a313</originalsourceid><addsrcrecordid>eNp1UE1Lw0AUXETBWv0B4iWgBz2k7mf27bEUrWJF29Tzskm2NrVt6m4K-u_dkFIE8fQezMybeYPQOcE9gom8TTHGChhAmJQCkweoQ7gkcQKcH6JOA8cNfoxOvF9gTKiguIOu-q70dVUvbVSto3puo1fryqqIridzW_ci1ovUzSk6mpmlt2e72UVv93fTwUM8ehk-DvqjOGdS1HGeBW_DreKUc6VkDkIobgsLYaESgAsjDTBqQDEoBFMFEzKjFBdMGUZYF122dzeu-txaX-tFtXXrYKkJVVzIhHAILNKycld57-xMb1y5Mu5bE6ybMvSfMoLmotUswrNuL0gYSN74xi0aqrBfe9S4D53I8JpOhmM9fRpT_JymehL4bJfArDJXFu_2V9B_M_wAVaNzow</addsrcrecordid><sourcetype>Aggregation Database</sourcetype><iscdi>true</iscdi><recordtype>article</recordtype><pqid>1294576148</pqid></control><display><type>article</type><title>Aristotle on the Period (Rhet. 3. 9)</title><source>JSTOR Archival Journals and Primary Sources Collection</source><source>Cambridge University Press:JISC Collections:Full Collection Digital Archives (STM and HSS) (218 titles)</source><creator>Fowler, R. L.</creator><creatorcontrib>Fowler, R. L.</creatorcontrib><description>Aristotle (Rhet. 3.9) distinguishes two types of style, the ‘periodic’ or ‘rounded’ (λ⋯ξιςκατεστραμμέη) and the ‘non-periodic’, ‘strung-on’ or ‘continuous’ (λέξιςε;ἰρομένη).* The latter is typical of prose in its young and unsophisticated state, and Aristotle is not much interested in it; his discussion of the periodic style is much longer, with subdivisions being introduced and numerous examples given. His basic definition of the period is not, however, clear, and the point has seen some controversy. There are two possibilities. (1) He defines the period ‘rhythmically’ (as I shall call it). The essential feature of the period is that its beginning and end are marked off by specific metrical rhythms (discussed in the preceding chapter, 3.8, where Aristotle recommends the paean).1 (2) He defines it ‘logically’. The period is a syntactic structure with an inner cohesion produced by the logical, pre-planned arrangement of its parts according to the requirements of the whole.2 The current consensus at least of written opinions is that Aristotle intended the first;3 I believe that the issue can be settled fairly decisively in favour of the second.</description><identifier>ISSN: 0009-8388</identifier><identifier>EISSN: 1471-6844</identifier><identifier>DOI: 10.1017/S0009838800022837</identifier><language>eng</language><publisher>Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press</publisher><subject>Antitheses ; Aristotelian rhetoric ; Aristotelianism ; Contradictories ; Oratory ; Peripateticism ; Poetry ; Sentences ; Terminology</subject><ispartof>Classical quarterly, 1982-01, Vol.32 (1), p.89-99</ispartof><rights>Copyright © The Classical Association 1982</rights><rights>Copyright 1982 Oxford University Press</rights><lds50>peer_reviewed</lds50><woscitedreferencessubscribed>false</woscitedreferencessubscribed><citedby>FETCH-LOGICAL-c375t-cb002a4e94244997c85594ede8855278845a7a832a8938d539d357b220d39a313</citedby></display><links><openurl>$$Topenurl_article</openurl><openurlfulltext>$$Topenurlfull_article</openurlfulltext><thumbnail>$$Tsyndetics_thumb_exl</thumbnail><linktopdf>$$Uhttps://www.jstor.org/stable/pdf/638741$$EPDF$$P50$$Gjstor$$H</linktopdf><linktohtml>$$Uhttps://www.cambridge.org/core/product/identifier/S0009838800022837/type/journal_article$$EHTML$$P50$$Gcambridge$$H</linktohtml><link.rule.ids>314,780,784,27923,27924,55688,58237,58470</link.rule.ids></links><search><creatorcontrib>Fowler, R. L.</creatorcontrib><title>Aristotle on the Period (Rhet. 3. 9)</title><title>Classical quarterly</title><addtitle>The Class. Q</addtitle><description>Aristotle (Rhet. 3.9) distinguishes two types of style, the ‘periodic’ or ‘rounded’ (λ⋯ξιςκατεστραμμέη) and the ‘non-periodic’, ‘strung-on’ or ‘continuous’ (λέξιςε;ἰρομένη).* The latter is typical of prose in its young and unsophisticated state, and Aristotle is not much interested in it; his discussion of the periodic style is much longer, with subdivisions being introduced and numerous examples given. His basic definition of the period is not, however, clear, and the point has seen some controversy. There are two possibilities. (1) He defines the period ‘rhythmically’ (as I shall call it). The essential feature of the period is that its beginning and end are marked off by specific metrical rhythms (discussed in the preceding chapter, 3.8, where Aristotle recommends the paean).1 (2) He defines it ‘logically’. The period is a syntactic structure with an inner cohesion produced by the logical, pre-planned arrangement of its parts according to the requirements of the whole.2 The current consensus at least of written opinions is that Aristotle intended the first;3 I believe that the issue can be settled fairly decisively in favour of the second.</description><subject>Antitheses</subject><subject>Aristotelian rhetoric</subject><subject>Aristotelianism</subject><subject>Contradictories</subject><subject>Oratory</subject><subject>Peripateticism</subject><subject>Poetry</subject><subject>Sentences</subject><subject>Terminology</subject><issn>0009-8388</issn><issn>1471-6844</issn><fulltext>true</fulltext><rsrctype>article</rsrctype><creationdate>1982</creationdate><recordtype>article</recordtype><recordid>eNp1UE1Lw0AUXETBWv0B4iWgBz2k7mf27bEUrWJF29Tzskm2NrVt6m4K-u_dkFIE8fQezMybeYPQOcE9gom8TTHGChhAmJQCkweoQ7gkcQKcH6JOA8cNfoxOvF9gTKiguIOu-q70dVUvbVSto3puo1fryqqIridzW_ci1ovUzSk6mpmlt2e72UVv93fTwUM8ehk-DvqjOGdS1HGeBW_DreKUc6VkDkIobgsLYaESgAsjDTBqQDEoBFMFEzKjFBdMGUZYF122dzeu-txaX-tFtXXrYKkJVVzIhHAILNKycld57-xMb1y5Mu5bE6ybMvSfMoLmotUswrNuL0gYSN74xi0aqrBfe9S4D53I8JpOhmM9fRpT_JymehL4bJfArDJXFu_2V9B_M_wAVaNzow</recordid><startdate>19820101</startdate><enddate>19820101</enddate><creator>Fowler, R. L.</creator><general>Cambridge University Press</general><general>Oxford University Press</general><general>Clarendon Press, etc</general><scope>BSCLL</scope><scope>AAYXX</scope><scope>CITATION</scope><scope>FBAQO</scope><scope>FUVTR</scope><scope>IOIBA</scope><scope>K30</scope><scope>PAAUG</scope><scope>PAWHS</scope><scope>PAWZZ</scope><scope>PAXOH</scope><scope>PBHAV</scope><scope>PBQSW</scope><scope>PBYQZ</scope><scope>PCIWU</scope><scope>PCMID</scope><scope>PCZJX</scope><scope>PDGRG</scope><scope>PDWWI</scope><scope>PETMR</scope><scope>PFVGT</scope><scope>PGXDX</scope><scope>PIHIL</scope><scope>PISVA</scope><scope>PJCTQ</scope><scope>PJTMS</scope><scope>PLCHJ</scope><scope>PMHAD</scope><scope>PNQDJ</scope><scope>POUND</scope><scope>PPLAD</scope><scope>PQAPC</scope><scope>PQCAN</scope><scope>PQCMW</scope><scope>PQEME</scope><scope>PQHKH</scope><scope>PQMID</scope><scope>PQNCT</scope><scope>PQNET</scope><scope>PQSCT</scope><scope>PQSET</scope><scope>PSVJG</scope><scope>PVMQY</scope><scope>PZGFC</scope></search><sort><creationdate>19820101</creationdate><title>Aristotle on the Period (Rhet. 3. 9)</title><author>Fowler, R. L.</author></sort><facets><frbrtype>5</frbrtype><frbrgroupid>cdi_FETCH-LOGICAL-c375t-cb002a4e94244997c85594ede8855278845a7a832a8938d539d357b220d39a313</frbrgroupid><rsrctype>articles</rsrctype><prefilter>articles</prefilter><language>eng</language><creationdate>1982</creationdate><topic>Antitheses</topic><topic>Aristotelian rhetoric</topic><topic>Aristotelianism</topic><topic>Contradictories</topic><topic>Oratory</topic><topic>Peripateticism</topic><topic>Poetry</topic><topic>Sentences</topic><topic>Terminology</topic><toplevel>peer_reviewed</toplevel><toplevel>online_resources</toplevel><creatorcontrib>Fowler, R. L.</creatorcontrib><collection>Istex</collection><collection>CrossRef</collection><collection>Periodicals Index Online Segment 02</collection><collection>Periodicals Index Online Segment 06</collection><collection>Periodicals Index Online Segment 29</collection><collection>Periodicals Index Online</collection><collection>Primary Sources Access—Foundation Edition (Plan E) - West</collection><collection>Primary Sources Access (Plan D) - International</collection><collection>Primary Sources Access & Build (Plan A) - MEA</collection><collection>Primary Sources Access—Foundation Edition (Plan E) - Midwest</collection><collection>Primary Sources Access—Foundation Edition (Plan E) - Northeast</collection><collection>Primary Sources Access (Plan D) - Southeast</collection><collection>Primary Sources Access (Plan D) - North Central</collection><collection>Primary Sources Access—Foundation Edition (Plan E) - Southeast</collection><collection>Primary Sources Access (Plan D) - South Central</collection><collection>Primary Sources Access & Build (Plan A) - UK / I</collection><collection>Primary Sources Access (Plan D) - Canada</collection><collection>Primary Sources Access (Plan D) - EMEALA</collection><collection>Primary Sources Access—Foundation Edition (Plan E) - North Central</collection><collection>Primary Sources Access—Foundation Edition (Plan E) - South Central</collection><collection>Primary Sources Access & Build (Plan A) - International</collection><collection>Primary Sources Access—Foundation Edition (Plan E) - International</collection><collection>Primary Sources Access (Plan D) - West</collection><collection>Periodicals Index Online Segments 1-50</collection><collection>Primary Sources Access (Plan D) - APAC</collection><collection>Primary Sources Access (Plan D) - Midwest</collection><collection>Primary Sources Access (Plan D) - MEA</collection><collection>Primary Sources Access—Foundation Edition (Plan E) - Canada</collection><collection>Primary Sources Access—Foundation Edition (Plan E) - UK / I</collection><collection>Primary Sources Access—Foundation Edition (Plan E) - EMEALA</collection><collection>Primary Sources Access & Build (Plan A) - APAC</collection><collection>Primary Sources Access & Build (Plan A) - Canada</collection><collection>Primary Sources Access & Build (Plan A) - West</collection><collection>Primary Sources Access & Build (Plan A) - EMEALA</collection><collection>Primary Sources Access (Plan D) - Northeast</collection><collection>Primary Sources Access & Build (Plan A) - Midwest</collection><collection>Primary Sources Access & Build (Plan A) - North Central</collection><collection>Primary Sources Access & Build (Plan A) - Northeast</collection><collection>Primary Sources Access & Build (Plan A) - South Central</collection><collection>Primary Sources Access & Build (Plan A) - Southeast</collection><collection>Primary Sources Access (Plan D) - UK / I</collection><collection>Primary Sources Access—Foundation Edition (Plan E) - APAC</collection><collection>Primary Sources Access—Foundation Edition (Plan E) - MEA</collection><jtitle>Classical quarterly</jtitle></facets><delivery><delcategory>Remote Search Resource</delcategory><fulltext>fulltext</fulltext></delivery><addata><au>Fowler, R. L.</au><format>journal</format><genre>article</genre><ristype>JOUR</ristype><atitle>Aristotle on the Period (Rhet. 3. 9)</atitle><jtitle>Classical quarterly</jtitle><addtitle>The Class. Q</addtitle><date>1982-01-01</date><risdate>1982</risdate><volume>32</volume><issue>1</issue><spage>89</spage><epage>99</epage><pages>89-99</pages><issn>0009-8388</issn><eissn>1471-6844</eissn><abstract>Aristotle (Rhet. 3.9) distinguishes two types of style, the ‘periodic’ or ‘rounded’ (λ⋯ξιςκατεστραμμέη) and the ‘non-periodic’, ‘strung-on’ or ‘continuous’ (λέξιςε;ἰρομένη).* The latter is typical of prose in its young and unsophisticated state, and Aristotle is not much interested in it; his discussion of the periodic style is much longer, with subdivisions being introduced and numerous examples given. His basic definition of the period is not, however, clear, and the point has seen some controversy. There are two possibilities. (1) He defines the period ‘rhythmically’ (as I shall call it). The essential feature of the period is that its beginning and end are marked off by specific metrical rhythms (discussed in the preceding chapter, 3.8, where Aristotle recommends the paean).1 (2) He defines it ‘logically’. The period is a syntactic structure with an inner cohesion produced by the logical, pre-planned arrangement of its parts according to the requirements of the whole.2 The current consensus at least of written opinions is that Aristotle intended the first;3 I believe that the issue can be settled fairly decisively in favour of the second.</abstract><cop>Cambridge, UK</cop><pub>Cambridge University Press</pub><doi>10.1017/S0009838800022837</doi><tpages>11</tpages></addata></record> |
fulltext | fulltext |
identifier | ISSN: 0009-8388 |
ispartof | Classical quarterly, 1982-01, Vol.32 (1), p.89-99 |
issn | 0009-8388 1471-6844 |
language | eng |
recordid | cdi_proquest_journals_1294576148 |
source | JSTOR Archival Journals and Primary Sources Collection; Cambridge University Press:JISC Collections:Full Collection Digital Archives (STM and HSS) (218 titles) |
subjects | Antitheses Aristotelian rhetoric Aristotelianism Contradictories Oratory Peripateticism Poetry Sentences Terminology |
title | Aristotle on the Period (Rhet. 3. 9) |
url | http://sfxeu10.hosted.exlibrisgroup.com/loughborough?ctx_ver=Z39.88-2004&ctx_enc=info:ofi/enc:UTF-8&ctx_tim=2025-01-08T17%3A54%3A31IST&url_ver=Z39.88-2004&url_ctx_fmt=infofi/fmt:kev:mtx:ctx&rfr_id=info:sid/primo.exlibrisgroup.com:primo3-Article-jstor_proqu&rft_val_fmt=info:ofi/fmt:kev:mtx:journal&rft.genre=article&rft.atitle=Aristotle%20on%20the%20Period%20(Rhet.%203.%209)&rft.jtitle=Classical%20quarterly&rft.au=Fowler,%20R.%20L.&rft.date=1982-01-01&rft.volume=32&rft.issue=1&rft.spage=89&rft.epage=99&rft.pages=89-99&rft.issn=0009-8388&rft.eissn=1471-6844&rft_id=info:doi/10.1017/S0009838800022837&rft_dat=%3Cjstor_proqu%3E638741%3C/jstor_proqu%3E%3Cgrp_id%3Ecdi_FETCH-LOGICAL-c375t-cb002a4e94244997c85594ede8855278845a7a832a8938d539d357b220d39a313%3C/grp_id%3E%3Coa%3E%3C/oa%3E%3Curl%3E%3C/url%3E&rft_id=info:oai/&rft_pqid=1294576148&rft_id=info:pmid/&rft_cupid=10_1017_S0009838800022837&rft_jstor_id=638741&rfr_iscdi=true |