Loading…
Ambiguous language and common priors
Standard economic models cannot capture the fact that information is often ambiguous, and is interpreted in multiple ways. Using a framework that distinguishes between the language in which statements are made and the interpretation of statements, we demonstrate that, unlike in the case where there...
Saved in:
Published in: | Games and economic behavior 2015-03, Vol.90, p.171-180 |
---|---|
Main Authors: | , |
Format: | Article |
Language: | English |
Subjects: | |
Citations: | Items that this one cites Items that cite this one |
Online Access: | Get full text |
Tags: |
Add Tag
No Tags, Be the first to tag this record!
|
cited_by | cdi_FETCH-LOGICAL-c432t-1620865dc7bd57ec9de0020db7248d275aa1cb95f2f1eea89b3660f921345a163 |
---|---|
cites | cdi_FETCH-LOGICAL-c432t-1620865dc7bd57ec9de0020db7248d275aa1cb95f2f1eea89b3660f921345a163 |
container_end_page | 180 |
container_issue | |
container_start_page | 171 |
container_title | Games and economic behavior |
container_volume | 90 |
creator | Halpern, Joseph Y. Kets, Willemien |
description | Standard economic models cannot capture the fact that information is often ambiguous, and is interpreted in multiple ways. Using a framework that distinguishes between the language in which statements are made and the interpretation of statements, we demonstrate that, unlike in the case where there is no ambiguity, players may come to have different beliefs starting from a common prior, even if they have received exactly the same information, unless the information is common knowledge. |
doi_str_mv | 10.1016/j.geb.2015.01.007 |
format | article |
fullrecord | <record><control><sourceid>proquest_cross</sourceid><recordid>TN_cdi_proquest_journals_1676466052</recordid><sourceformat>XML</sourceformat><sourcesystem>PC</sourcesystem><els_id>S0899825615000342</els_id><sourcerecordid>3669034971</sourcerecordid><originalsourceid>FETCH-LOGICAL-c432t-1620865dc7bd57ec9de0020db7248d275aa1cb95f2f1eea89b3660f921345a163</originalsourceid><addsrcrecordid>eNp9kE1LxDAURYMoOI7-AHcF3ba-lzZJg6th8AsG3Og6pElaWqbNmLSC_94M49rV25x73-UQcotQICB_GIrONQUFZAVgASDOyApBQk4rUZ6TFdRS5jVl_JJcxTgAAKMCVuR-MzZ9t_glZns9dYvuXKYnmxk_jn7KDqH3IV6Ti1bvo7v5u2vy-fz0sX3Nd-8vb9vNLjdVSeccOYWaM2tEY5lwRloHQME2gla1pYJpjaaRrKUtOqdr2ZScQysplhXTyMs1uTv1HoL_Wlyc1eCXMKWXCrngVaIZTRSeKBN8jMG1Kq0cdfhRCOooQw0qyVBHGQpQJRkp83jKuDT_u3dBRdO7yTjbB2dmZX3_T_oXmstlDA</addsrcrecordid><sourcetype>Aggregation Database</sourcetype><iscdi>true</iscdi><recordtype>article</recordtype><pqid>1676466052</pqid></control><display><type>article</type><title>Ambiguous language and common priors</title><source>International Bibliography of the Social Sciences (IBSS)</source><source>ScienceDirect Journals</source><creator>Halpern, Joseph Y. ; Kets, Willemien</creator><creatorcontrib>Halpern, Joseph Y. ; Kets, Willemien</creatorcontrib><description>Standard economic models cannot capture the fact that information is often ambiguous, and is interpreted in multiple ways. Using a framework that distinguishes between the language in which statements are made and the interpretation of statements, we demonstrate that, unlike in the case where there is no ambiguity, players may come to have different beliefs starting from a common prior, even if they have received exactly the same information, unless the information is common knowledge.</description><identifier>ISSN: 0899-8256</identifier><identifier>EISSN: 1090-2473</identifier><identifier>DOI: 10.1016/j.geb.2015.01.007</identifier><language>eng</language><publisher>Duluth: Elsevier Inc</publisher><subject>Agree to disagree ; Ambiguous language ; Common prior ; Economic models ; Game theory ; Harsanyi doctrine ; Language ; Studies</subject><ispartof>Games and economic behavior, 2015-03, Vol.90, p.171-180</ispartof><rights>2015 Elsevier Inc.</rights><rights>Copyright Academic Press Mar 2015</rights><lds50>peer_reviewed</lds50><oa>free_for_read</oa><woscitedreferencessubscribed>false</woscitedreferencessubscribed><citedby>FETCH-LOGICAL-c432t-1620865dc7bd57ec9de0020db7248d275aa1cb95f2f1eea89b3660f921345a163</citedby><cites>FETCH-LOGICAL-c432t-1620865dc7bd57ec9de0020db7248d275aa1cb95f2f1eea89b3660f921345a163</cites><orcidid>0000-0002-4914-9426</orcidid></display><links><openurl>$$Topenurl_article</openurl><openurlfulltext>$$Topenurlfull_article</openurlfulltext><thumbnail>$$Tsyndetics_thumb_exl</thumbnail><link.rule.ids>314,780,784,27924,27925,33223</link.rule.ids></links><search><creatorcontrib>Halpern, Joseph Y.</creatorcontrib><creatorcontrib>Kets, Willemien</creatorcontrib><title>Ambiguous language and common priors</title><title>Games and economic behavior</title><description>Standard economic models cannot capture the fact that information is often ambiguous, and is interpreted in multiple ways. Using a framework that distinguishes between the language in which statements are made and the interpretation of statements, we demonstrate that, unlike in the case where there is no ambiguity, players may come to have different beliefs starting from a common prior, even if they have received exactly the same information, unless the information is common knowledge.</description><subject>Agree to disagree</subject><subject>Ambiguous language</subject><subject>Common prior</subject><subject>Economic models</subject><subject>Game theory</subject><subject>Harsanyi doctrine</subject><subject>Language</subject><subject>Studies</subject><issn>0899-8256</issn><issn>1090-2473</issn><fulltext>true</fulltext><rsrctype>article</rsrctype><creationdate>2015</creationdate><recordtype>article</recordtype><sourceid>8BJ</sourceid><recordid>eNp9kE1LxDAURYMoOI7-AHcF3ba-lzZJg6th8AsG3Og6pElaWqbNmLSC_94M49rV25x73-UQcotQICB_GIrONQUFZAVgASDOyApBQk4rUZ6TFdRS5jVl_JJcxTgAAKMCVuR-MzZ9t_glZns9dYvuXKYnmxk_jn7KDqH3IV6Ti1bvo7v5u2vy-fz0sX3Nd-8vb9vNLjdVSeccOYWaM2tEY5lwRloHQME2gla1pYJpjaaRrKUtOqdr2ZScQysplhXTyMs1uTv1HoL_Wlyc1eCXMKWXCrngVaIZTRSeKBN8jMG1Kq0cdfhRCOooQw0qyVBHGQpQJRkp83jKuDT_u3dBRdO7yTjbB2dmZX3_T_oXmstlDA</recordid><startdate>20150301</startdate><enddate>20150301</enddate><creator>Halpern, Joseph Y.</creator><creator>Kets, Willemien</creator><general>Elsevier Inc</general><general>Academic Press</general><scope>AAYXX</scope><scope>CITATION</scope><scope>8BJ</scope><scope>FQK</scope><scope>JBE</scope><orcidid>https://orcid.org/0000-0002-4914-9426</orcidid></search><sort><creationdate>20150301</creationdate><title>Ambiguous language and common priors</title><author>Halpern, Joseph Y. ; Kets, Willemien</author></sort><facets><frbrtype>5</frbrtype><frbrgroupid>cdi_FETCH-LOGICAL-c432t-1620865dc7bd57ec9de0020db7248d275aa1cb95f2f1eea89b3660f921345a163</frbrgroupid><rsrctype>articles</rsrctype><prefilter>articles</prefilter><language>eng</language><creationdate>2015</creationdate><topic>Agree to disagree</topic><topic>Ambiguous language</topic><topic>Common prior</topic><topic>Economic models</topic><topic>Game theory</topic><topic>Harsanyi doctrine</topic><topic>Language</topic><topic>Studies</topic><toplevel>peer_reviewed</toplevel><toplevel>online_resources</toplevel><creatorcontrib>Halpern, Joseph Y.</creatorcontrib><creatorcontrib>Kets, Willemien</creatorcontrib><collection>CrossRef</collection><collection>International Bibliography of the Social Sciences (IBSS)</collection><collection>International Bibliography of the Social Sciences</collection><collection>International Bibliography of the Social Sciences</collection><jtitle>Games and economic behavior</jtitle></facets><delivery><delcategory>Remote Search Resource</delcategory><fulltext>fulltext</fulltext></delivery><addata><au>Halpern, Joseph Y.</au><au>Kets, Willemien</au><format>journal</format><genre>article</genre><ristype>JOUR</ristype><atitle>Ambiguous language and common priors</atitle><jtitle>Games and economic behavior</jtitle><date>2015-03-01</date><risdate>2015</risdate><volume>90</volume><spage>171</spage><epage>180</epage><pages>171-180</pages><issn>0899-8256</issn><eissn>1090-2473</eissn><abstract>Standard economic models cannot capture the fact that information is often ambiguous, and is interpreted in multiple ways. Using a framework that distinguishes between the language in which statements are made and the interpretation of statements, we demonstrate that, unlike in the case where there is no ambiguity, players may come to have different beliefs starting from a common prior, even if they have received exactly the same information, unless the information is common knowledge.</abstract><cop>Duluth</cop><pub>Elsevier Inc</pub><doi>10.1016/j.geb.2015.01.007</doi><tpages>10</tpages><orcidid>https://orcid.org/0000-0002-4914-9426</orcidid><oa>free_for_read</oa></addata></record> |
fulltext | fulltext |
identifier | ISSN: 0899-8256 |
ispartof | Games and economic behavior, 2015-03, Vol.90, p.171-180 |
issn | 0899-8256 1090-2473 |
language | eng |
recordid | cdi_proquest_journals_1676466052 |
source | International Bibliography of the Social Sciences (IBSS); ScienceDirect Journals |
subjects | Agree to disagree Ambiguous language Common prior Economic models Game theory Harsanyi doctrine Language Studies |
title | Ambiguous language and common priors |
url | http://sfxeu10.hosted.exlibrisgroup.com/loughborough?ctx_ver=Z39.88-2004&ctx_enc=info:ofi/enc:UTF-8&ctx_tim=2025-01-06T19%3A11%3A07IST&url_ver=Z39.88-2004&url_ctx_fmt=infofi/fmt:kev:mtx:ctx&rfr_id=info:sid/primo.exlibrisgroup.com:primo3-Article-proquest_cross&rft_val_fmt=info:ofi/fmt:kev:mtx:journal&rft.genre=article&rft.atitle=Ambiguous%20language%20and%20common%20priors&rft.jtitle=Games%20and%20economic%20behavior&rft.au=Halpern,%20Joseph%20Y.&rft.date=2015-03-01&rft.volume=90&rft.spage=171&rft.epage=180&rft.pages=171-180&rft.issn=0899-8256&rft.eissn=1090-2473&rft_id=info:doi/10.1016/j.geb.2015.01.007&rft_dat=%3Cproquest_cross%3E3669034971%3C/proquest_cross%3E%3Cgrp_id%3Ecdi_FETCH-LOGICAL-c432t-1620865dc7bd57ec9de0020db7248d275aa1cb95f2f1eea89b3660f921345a163%3C/grp_id%3E%3Coa%3E%3C/oa%3E%3Curl%3E%3C/url%3E&rft_id=info:oai/&rft_pqid=1676466052&rft_id=info:pmid/&rfr_iscdi=true |