Loading…
Which practical interventions does the do-operator refer to in causal inference? Illustration on the example of obesity and cancer
For exposures \(X\) like obesity, no precise and unambiguous definition exists for the hypothetical intervention \(do(X = x_0)\). This has raised concerns about the relevance of causal effects estimated from observational studies for such exposures. Under the framework of structural causal models, w...
Saved in:
Published in: | arXiv.org 2019-01 |
---|---|
Main Authors: | , |
Format: | Article |
Language: | English |
Subjects: | |
Online Access: | Get full text |
Tags: |
Add Tag
No Tags, Be the first to tag this record!
|
cited_by | |
---|---|
cites | |
container_end_page | |
container_issue | |
container_start_page | |
container_title | arXiv.org |
container_volume | |
creator | Etievant, Lola Viallon, Vivian |
description | For exposures \(X\) like obesity, no precise and unambiguous definition exists for the hypothetical intervention \(do(X = x_0)\). This has raised concerns about the relevance of causal effects estimated from observational studies for such exposures. Under the framework of structural causal models, we study how the effect of \(do(X = x_0)\) relates to the effect of interventions on causes of \(X\). We show that for interventions focusing on causes of \(X\) that affect the outcome through \(X\) only, the effect of \(do(X = x_0)\) equals the effect of the considered intervention. On the other hand, for interventions on causes \(W\) of \(X\) that affect the outcome not only through \(X\), we show that the effect of \(do(X = x_0)\) only partly captures the effect of the intervention. In particular, under simple causal models (e.g., linear models with no interaction), the effect of \(do(X = x_0)\) can be seen as an indirect effect of the intervention on \(W\). |
format | article |
fullrecord | <record><control><sourceid>proquest</sourceid><recordid>TN_cdi_proquest_journals_2163287798</recordid><sourceformat>XML</sourceformat><sourcesystem>PC</sourcesystem><sourcerecordid>2163287798</sourcerecordid><originalsourceid>FETCH-proquest_journals_21632877983</originalsourceid><addsrcrecordid>eNqNjMFKA0EMhoeCYNG-Q8DzwnbGdtdTD0XRu-CxjNMsO2WcbJOs6NUnN4oPIAT-n-T7snBLH8K66W-9v3QrkVPbtn7b-c0mLN3Xy5jTCBPHpDnFArkq8jtWzVQFjoQCOqKVhibkqMTAOCCDkrGQ4iy_lq2wJtzBUymzqJH2AGx-bPyIb1NBoAHoFSXrJ8R6NNkMvnYXQyyCq7-8cjcP98_7x2ZiOs8oejjRzNVOB7_eBt933V0f_kd9AzIaUgM</addsrcrecordid><sourcetype>Aggregation Database</sourcetype><iscdi>true</iscdi><recordtype>article</recordtype><pqid>2163287798</pqid></control><display><type>article</type><title>Which practical interventions does the do-operator refer to in causal inference? Illustration on the example of obesity and cancer</title><source>Publicly Available Content Database</source><creator>Etievant, Lola ; Viallon, Vivian</creator><creatorcontrib>Etievant, Lola ; Viallon, Vivian</creatorcontrib><description>For exposures \(X\) like obesity, no precise and unambiguous definition exists for the hypothetical intervention \(do(X = x_0)\). This has raised concerns about the relevance of causal effects estimated from observational studies for such exposures. Under the framework of structural causal models, we study how the effect of \(do(X = x_0)\) relates to the effect of interventions on causes of \(X\). We show that for interventions focusing on causes of \(X\) that affect the outcome through \(X\) only, the effect of \(do(X = x_0)\) equals the effect of the considered intervention. On the other hand, for interventions on causes \(W\) of \(X\) that affect the outcome not only through \(X\), we show that the effect of \(do(X = x_0)\) only partly captures the effect of the intervention. In particular, under simple causal models (e.g., linear models with no interaction), the effect of \(do(X = x_0)\) can be seen as an indirect effect of the intervention on \(W\).</description><identifier>EISSN: 2331-8422</identifier><language>eng</language><publisher>Ithaca: Cornell University Library, arXiv.org</publisher><subject>Intervention ; Obesity</subject><ispartof>arXiv.org, 2019-01</ispartof><rights>2019. This work is published under http://arxiv.org/licenses/nonexclusive-distrib/1.0/ (the “License”). Notwithstanding the ProQuest Terms and Conditions, you may use this content in accordance with the terms of the License.</rights><oa>free_for_read</oa><woscitedreferencessubscribed>false</woscitedreferencessubscribed></display><links><openurl>$$Topenurl_article</openurl><openurlfulltext>$$Topenurlfull_article</openurlfulltext><thumbnail>$$Tsyndetics_thumb_exl</thumbnail><linktohtml>$$Uhttps://www.proquest.com/docview/2163287798?pq-origsite=primo$$EHTML$$P50$$Gproquest$$Hfree_for_read</linktohtml><link.rule.ids>776,780,25731,36989,44566</link.rule.ids></links><search><creatorcontrib>Etievant, Lola</creatorcontrib><creatorcontrib>Viallon, Vivian</creatorcontrib><title>Which practical interventions does the do-operator refer to in causal inference? Illustration on the example of obesity and cancer</title><title>arXiv.org</title><description>For exposures \(X\) like obesity, no precise and unambiguous definition exists for the hypothetical intervention \(do(X = x_0)\). This has raised concerns about the relevance of causal effects estimated from observational studies for such exposures. Under the framework of structural causal models, we study how the effect of \(do(X = x_0)\) relates to the effect of interventions on causes of \(X\). We show that for interventions focusing on causes of \(X\) that affect the outcome through \(X\) only, the effect of \(do(X = x_0)\) equals the effect of the considered intervention. On the other hand, for interventions on causes \(W\) of \(X\) that affect the outcome not only through \(X\), we show that the effect of \(do(X = x_0)\) only partly captures the effect of the intervention. In particular, under simple causal models (e.g., linear models with no interaction), the effect of \(do(X = x_0)\) can be seen as an indirect effect of the intervention on \(W\).</description><subject>Intervention</subject><subject>Obesity</subject><issn>2331-8422</issn><fulltext>true</fulltext><rsrctype>article</rsrctype><creationdate>2019</creationdate><recordtype>article</recordtype><sourceid>PIMPY</sourceid><recordid>eNqNjMFKA0EMhoeCYNG-Q8DzwnbGdtdTD0XRu-CxjNMsO2WcbJOs6NUnN4oPIAT-n-T7snBLH8K66W-9v3QrkVPbtn7b-c0mLN3Xy5jTCBPHpDnFArkq8jtWzVQFjoQCOqKVhibkqMTAOCCDkrGQ4iy_lq2wJtzBUymzqJH2AGx-bPyIb1NBoAHoFSXrJ8R6NNkMvnYXQyyCq7-8cjcP98_7x2ZiOs8oejjRzNVOB7_eBt933V0f_kd9AzIaUgM</recordid><startdate>20190103</startdate><enddate>20190103</enddate><creator>Etievant, Lola</creator><creator>Viallon, Vivian</creator><general>Cornell University Library, arXiv.org</general><scope>8FE</scope><scope>8FG</scope><scope>ABJCF</scope><scope>ABUWG</scope><scope>AFKRA</scope><scope>AZQEC</scope><scope>BENPR</scope><scope>BGLVJ</scope><scope>CCPQU</scope><scope>DWQXO</scope><scope>HCIFZ</scope><scope>L6V</scope><scope>M7S</scope><scope>PIMPY</scope><scope>PQEST</scope><scope>PQQKQ</scope><scope>PQUKI</scope><scope>PRINS</scope><scope>PTHSS</scope></search><sort><creationdate>20190103</creationdate><title>Which practical interventions does the do-operator refer to in causal inference? Illustration on the example of obesity and cancer</title><author>Etievant, Lola ; Viallon, Vivian</author></sort><facets><frbrtype>5</frbrtype><frbrgroupid>cdi_FETCH-proquest_journals_21632877983</frbrgroupid><rsrctype>articles</rsrctype><prefilter>articles</prefilter><language>eng</language><creationdate>2019</creationdate><topic>Intervention</topic><topic>Obesity</topic><toplevel>online_resources</toplevel><creatorcontrib>Etievant, Lola</creatorcontrib><creatorcontrib>Viallon, Vivian</creatorcontrib><collection>ProQuest SciTech Collection</collection><collection>ProQuest Technology Collection</collection><collection>Materials Science & Engineering Collection</collection><collection>ProQuest Central (Alumni)</collection><collection>ProQuest Central</collection><collection>ProQuest Central Essentials</collection><collection>ProQuest Central</collection><collection>Technology Collection</collection><collection>ProQuest One Community College</collection><collection>ProQuest Central</collection><collection>SciTech Premium Collection</collection><collection>ProQuest Engineering Collection</collection><collection>Engineering Database</collection><collection>Publicly Available Content Database</collection><collection>ProQuest One Academic Eastern Edition (DO NOT USE)</collection><collection>ProQuest One Academic</collection><collection>ProQuest One Academic UKI Edition</collection><collection>ProQuest Central China</collection><collection>Engineering Collection</collection></facets><delivery><delcategory>Remote Search Resource</delcategory><fulltext>fulltext</fulltext></delivery><addata><au>Etievant, Lola</au><au>Viallon, Vivian</au><format>book</format><genre>document</genre><ristype>GEN</ristype><atitle>Which practical interventions does the do-operator refer to in causal inference? Illustration on the example of obesity and cancer</atitle><jtitle>arXiv.org</jtitle><date>2019-01-03</date><risdate>2019</risdate><eissn>2331-8422</eissn><abstract>For exposures \(X\) like obesity, no precise and unambiguous definition exists for the hypothetical intervention \(do(X = x_0)\). This has raised concerns about the relevance of causal effects estimated from observational studies for such exposures. Under the framework of structural causal models, we study how the effect of \(do(X = x_0)\) relates to the effect of interventions on causes of \(X\). We show that for interventions focusing on causes of \(X\) that affect the outcome through \(X\) only, the effect of \(do(X = x_0)\) equals the effect of the considered intervention. On the other hand, for interventions on causes \(W\) of \(X\) that affect the outcome not only through \(X\), we show that the effect of \(do(X = x_0)\) only partly captures the effect of the intervention. In particular, under simple causal models (e.g., linear models with no interaction), the effect of \(do(X = x_0)\) can be seen as an indirect effect of the intervention on \(W\).</abstract><cop>Ithaca</cop><pub>Cornell University Library, arXiv.org</pub><oa>free_for_read</oa></addata></record> |
fulltext | fulltext |
identifier | EISSN: 2331-8422 |
ispartof | arXiv.org, 2019-01 |
issn | 2331-8422 |
language | eng |
recordid | cdi_proquest_journals_2163287798 |
source | Publicly Available Content Database |
subjects | Intervention Obesity |
title | Which practical interventions does the do-operator refer to in causal inference? Illustration on the example of obesity and cancer |
url | http://sfxeu10.hosted.exlibrisgroup.com/loughborough?ctx_ver=Z39.88-2004&ctx_enc=info:ofi/enc:UTF-8&ctx_tim=2025-02-13T23%3A20%3A20IST&url_ver=Z39.88-2004&url_ctx_fmt=infofi/fmt:kev:mtx:ctx&rfr_id=info:sid/primo.exlibrisgroup.com:primo3-Article-proquest&rft_val_fmt=info:ofi/fmt:kev:mtx:book&rft.genre=document&rft.atitle=Which%20practical%20interventions%20does%20the%20do-operator%20refer%20to%20in%20causal%20inference?%20Illustration%20on%20the%20example%20of%20obesity%20and%20cancer&rft.jtitle=arXiv.org&rft.au=Etievant,%20Lola&rft.date=2019-01-03&rft.eissn=2331-8422&rft_id=info:doi/&rft_dat=%3Cproquest%3E2163287798%3C/proquest%3E%3Cgrp_id%3Ecdi_FETCH-proquest_journals_21632877983%3C/grp_id%3E%3Coa%3E%3C/oa%3E%3Curl%3E%3C/url%3E&rft_id=info:oai/&rft_pqid=2163287798&rft_id=info:pmid/&rfr_iscdi=true |