Loading…

Two Rules of Legality in Criminal Law

Criminal law scholars approach legality in various ways. Some scholars eschew over-arching principles and proceed directly to one or more distinct "rules": (1) the rule against retroactive criminalization; (2) the rule that criminal statutes be construed narrowly; (3) the rule against the...

Full description

Saved in:
Bibliographic Details
Published in:Law and philosophy 2007-05, Vol.26 (3), p.229-305
Main Author: Westen, Peter
Format: Article
Language:English
Subjects:
Citations: Items that cite this one
Online Access:Get full text
Tags: Add Tag
No Tags, Be the first to tag this record!
cited_by cdi_FETCH-LOGICAL-c356t-ca4b6ef56b9c4fa9f3ec508ce154ca89e9fec2246eb7f6268dd7d13fc45360633
cites
container_end_page 305
container_issue 3
container_start_page 229
container_title Law and philosophy
container_volume 26
creator Westen, Peter
description Criminal law scholars approach legality in various ways. Some scholars eschew over-arching principles and proceed directly to one or more distinct "rules": (1) the rule against retroactive criminalization; (2) the rule that criminal statutes be construed narrowly; (3) the rule against the judicial creation of common-law offenses; and (4) the rule that vague criminal statutes are void. Other scholars seek a single principle, i.e., the "principal of legality," that they claim underlies the four rules. In contrast, I believe that both approaches are misguided. There is no such thing as a single "principle of legality;" yet, the four aforementioned rules are not unrelated to each other. The so-called "principle of legality" consists of two distinct norms that derive, respectively, from two fundamental principles of criminal justice, viz., the principle, "No person shall be punished in the absence of a bad mind," and the principle that underlies the maxim, "Every person is presumed innocent until proven guilty." The first norm of legality explains the rules regarding ex post facto legislation, and rules regarding "notice" and "fair warning" of judicial decisions. When a person is punished for violating a rule that was non-existent or unclear at the time he acted, he is punished for conduct that the state now condemns and seeks to prevent by means of penal sanctions. Accordingly, at the time the person is prosecuted, his claim is not that he did not do anything that the state regards as wrong, but, rather, that he neither knew nor should have known that he was doing something that the state would come to regard as wrong. He ought, indeed, to be excused for his mistake, but only because of a principle that is common to excuses generally: "No person ought to be punished in the absence of a guilty mind." He should be excused because even when a person does something the state condemns and seeks to prevent, he ought not to be blamed for it unless he was motivated in a certain way, namely, by an attitude of disrespect for the legitimate interests of the political community by whose norms he is bound. The Second norm of legality informs several of the remaining rules, though not all of them. The second norm is that a person ought not to be punished in the name of a political community unless it can confidently be said that the community officially regards his conduct as warranting the criminal punishment at issue. It is a norm that is most commonly associated with the
doi_str_mv 10.1007/s10982-006-0007-7
format article
fullrecord <record><control><sourceid>jstor_proqu</sourceid><recordid>TN_cdi_proquest_miscellaneous_36662654</recordid><sourceformat>XML</sourceformat><sourcesystem>PC</sourcesystem><jstor_id>27652617</jstor_id><sourcerecordid>27652617</sourcerecordid><originalsourceid>FETCH-LOGICAL-c356t-ca4b6ef56b9c4fa9f3ec508ce154ca89e9fec2246eb7f6268dd7d13fc45360633</originalsourceid><addsrcrecordid>eNo9kE1LAzEQQIMoWKs_wIOwF71F8znZHKVYFRYEqeeQzU5ky7ZbN1tK_70pKx6Gubw3DI-QW84eOWPmKXFmS0EZgzzMUHNGZlwbSZkW4pzMGAdDtVD2klyltM6MLRnMyP3q0Bef-w5T0ceiwm_fteOxaLfFYmg37dZ3ReUP1-Qi-i7hzd-ek6_ly2rxRquP1_fFc0WD1DDS4FUNGDXUNqjobZQYNCsDcq2CLy3aiEEIBVibCALKpjENlzEoLYGBlHPyMN3dDf3PHtPoNm0K2HV-i_0-OQmQNa0yyCcwDH1KA0a3y-_64eg4c6cgbgrichB3CuJMdu4mZ53GfvgXhAEtgBv5Cw8ZW7w</addsrcrecordid><sourcetype>Aggregation Database</sourcetype><iscdi>true</iscdi><recordtype>article</recordtype><pqid>36662654</pqid></control><display><type>article</type><title>Two Rules of Legality in Criminal Law</title><source>International Bibliography of the Social Sciences (IBSS)</source><source>JSTOR Archival Journals and Primary Sources Collection</source><source>Springer Link</source><creator>Westen, Peter</creator><creatorcontrib>Westen, Peter</creatorcontrib><description>Criminal law scholars approach legality in various ways. Some scholars eschew over-arching principles and proceed directly to one or more distinct "rules": (1) the rule against retroactive criminalization; (2) the rule that criminal statutes be construed narrowly; (3) the rule against the judicial creation of common-law offenses; and (4) the rule that vague criminal statutes are void. Other scholars seek a single principle, i.e., the "principal of legality," that they claim underlies the four rules. In contrast, I believe that both approaches are misguided. There is no such thing as a single "principle of legality;" yet, the four aforementioned rules are not unrelated to each other. The so-called "principle of legality" consists of two distinct norms that derive, respectively, from two fundamental principles of criminal justice, viz., the principle, "No person shall be punished in the absence of a bad mind," and the principle that underlies the maxim, "Every person is presumed innocent until proven guilty." The first norm of legality explains the rules regarding ex post facto legislation, and rules regarding "notice" and "fair warning" of judicial decisions. When a person is punished for violating a rule that was non-existent or unclear at the time he acted, he is punished for conduct that the state now condemns and seeks to prevent by means of penal sanctions. Accordingly, at the time the person is prosecuted, his claim is not that he did not do anything that the state regards as wrong, but, rather, that he neither knew nor should have known that he was doing something that the state would come to regard as wrong. He ought, indeed, to be excused for his mistake, but only because of a principle that is common to excuses generally: "No person ought to be punished in the absence of a guilty mind." He should be excused because even when a person does something the state condemns and seeks to prevent, he ought not to be blamed for it unless he was motivated in a certain way, namely, by an attitude of disrespect for the legitimate interests of the political community by whose norms he is bound. The Second norm of legality informs several of the remaining rules, though not all of them. The second norm is that a person ought not to be punished in the name of a political community unless it can confidently be said that the community officially regards his conduct as warranting the criminal punishment at issue. It is a norm that is most commonly associated with the rule of lenity, but it is not confined to the construction of statutes that are ambiguous or vague. It can also be also violated when a person is punished for violating a statute that has fallen into desuetude, regardless of how widely promulgated or narrowly defined the statute may be. This second norm derives from a principle that also underlies the presumption of innocence — the only difference being that the presumption of innocence is a preference for acquittal in the event of uncertainty regarding the facts which an actor is charged, while the second norm of legality is a preference for acquittal in the event of uncertainty regarding the scope of the offense which he is charged. Nevertheless, one "rule " remains that this analysis throws into question — namely, the rule that "vague" criminal statutes are void. Criminal statutes are sometimes so broadly defined that they do, indeed, infringe constitutionally protected rights of speech, movement, etc. — in which event they ought to be invalidated on those very grounds. And criminal statutes are sometimes so broadly drafted that, before applying them, courts ought to construe them to apply only to constitutionally unprotected acts that courts can confidently say the relevant political community regards as warranting punishment. But once statutes are so construed to apply only to constitutionally unprotected conduct, courts have no further reason to invalidate them because, with respect to the narrowly defined conduct such statutes are construed to prohibit, "common social duty" alone ought to alert actors that their conduct is suspect.</description><identifier>ISSN: 0167-5249</identifier><identifier>EISSN: 1573-0522</identifier><identifier>DOI: 10.1007/s10982-006-0007-7</identifier><language>eng</language><publisher>Springer</publisher><subject>Criminal justice ; Criminal law ; Criminal legislation ; Criminal offenses ; Criminality ; Criminals ; Defendants ; Legal science ; Legislation ; Offenders ; Philosophy of law ; Punishment ; Regulation ; Rule of law ; Statutory interpretation ; Statutory law</subject><ispartof>Law and philosophy, 2007-05, Vol.26 (3), p.229-305</ispartof><rights>Copyright 2006 Springer</rights><lds50>peer_reviewed</lds50><woscitedreferencessubscribed>false</woscitedreferencessubscribed><citedby>FETCH-LOGICAL-c356t-ca4b6ef56b9c4fa9f3ec508ce154ca89e9fec2246eb7f6268dd7d13fc45360633</citedby></display><links><openurl>$$Topenurl_article</openurl><openurlfulltext>$$Topenurlfull_article</openurlfulltext><thumbnail>$$Tsyndetics_thumb_exl</thumbnail><linktopdf>$$Uhttps://www.jstor.org/stable/pdf/27652617$$EPDF$$P50$$Gjstor$$H</linktopdf><linktohtml>$$Uhttps://www.jstor.org/stable/27652617$$EHTML$$P50$$Gjstor$$H</linktohtml><link.rule.ids>314,780,784,27924,27925,33224,58238,58471</link.rule.ids></links><search><creatorcontrib>Westen, Peter</creatorcontrib><title>Two Rules of Legality in Criminal Law</title><title>Law and philosophy</title><description>Criminal law scholars approach legality in various ways. Some scholars eschew over-arching principles and proceed directly to one or more distinct "rules": (1) the rule against retroactive criminalization; (2) the rule that criminal statutes be construed narrowly; (3) the rule against the judicial creation of common-law offenses; and (4) the rule that vague criminal statutes are void. Other scholars seek a single principle, i.e., the "principal of legality," that they claim underlies the four rules. In contrast, I believe that both approaches are misguided. There is no such thing as a single "principle of legality;" yet, the four aforementioned rules are not unrelated to each other. The so-called "principle of legality" consists of two distinct norms that derive, respectively, from two fundamental principles of criminal justice, viz., the principle, "No person shall be punished in the absence of a bad mind," and the principle that underlies the maxim, "Every person is presumed innocent until proven guilty." The first norm of legality explains the rules regarding ex post facto legislation, and rules regarding "notice" and "fair warning" of judicial decisions. When a person is punished for violating a rule that was non-existent or unclear at the time he acted, he is punished for conduct that the state now condemns and seeks to prevent by means of penal sanctions. Accordingly, at the time the person is prosecuted, his claim is not that he did not do anything that the state regards as wrong, but, rather, that he neither knew nor should have known that he was doing something that the state would come to regard as wrong. He ought, indeed, to be excused for his mistake, but only because of a principle that is common to excuses generally: "No person ought to be punished in the absence of a guilty mind." He should be excused because even when a person does something the state condemns and seeks to prevent, he ought not to be blamed for it unless he was motivated in a certain way, namely, by an attitude of disrespect for the legitimate interests of the political community by whose norms he is bound. The Second norm of legality informs several of the remaining rules, though not all of them. The second norm is that a person ought not to be punished in the name of a political community unless it can confidently be said that the community officially regards his conduct as warranting the criminal punishment at issue. It is a norm that is most commonly associated with the rule of lenity, but it is not confined to the construction of statutes that are ambiguous or vague. It can also be also violated when a person is punished for violating a statute that has fallen into desuetude, regardless of how widely promulgated or narrowly defined the statute may be. This second norm derives from a principle that also underlies the presumption of innocence — the only difference being that the presumption of innocence is a preference for acquittal in the event of uncertainty regarding the facts which an actor is charged, while the second norm of legality is a preference for acquittal in the event of uncertainty regarding the scope of the offense which he is charged. Nevertheless, one "rule " remains that this analysis throws into question — namely, the rule that "vague" criminal statutes are void. Criminal statutes are sometimes so broadly defined that they do, indeed, infringe constitutionally protected rights of speech, movement, etc. — in which event they ought to be invalidated on those very grounds. And criminal statutes are sometimes so broadly drafted that, before applying them, courts ought to construe them to apply only to constitutionally unprotected acts that courts can confidently say the relevant political community regards as warranting punishment. But once statutes are so construed to apply only to constitutionally unprotected conduct, courts have no further reason to invalidate them because, with respect to the narrowly defined conduct such statutes are construed to prohibit, "common social duty" alone ought to alert actors that their conduct is suspect.</description><subject>Criminal justice</subject><subject>Criminal law</subject><subject>Criminal legislation</subject><subject>Criminal offenses</subject><subject>Criminality</subject><subject>Criminals</subject><subject>Defendants</subject><subject>Legal science</subject><subject>Legislation</subject><subject>Offenders</subject><subject>Philosophy of law</subject><subject>Punishment</subject><subject>Regulation</subject><subject>Rule of law</subject><subject>Statutory interpretation</subject><subject>Statutory law</subject><issn>0167-5249</issn><issn>1573-0522</issn><fulltext>true</fulltext><rsrctype>article</rsrctype><creationdate>2007</creationdate><recordtype>article</recordtype><sourceid>8BJ</sourceid><recordid>eNo9kE1LAzEQQIMoWKs_wIOwF71F8znZHKVYFRYEqeeQzU5ky7ZbN1tK_70pKx6Gubw3DI-QW84eOWPmKXFmS0EZgzzMUHNGZlwbSZkW4pzMGAdDtVD2klyltM6MLRnMyP3q0Bef-w5T0ceiwm_fteOxaLfFYmg37dZ3ReUP1-Qi-i7hzd-ek6_ly2rxRquP1_fFc0WD1DDS4FUNGDXUNqjobZQYNCsDcq2CLy3aiEEIBVibCALKpjENlzEoLYGBlHPyMN3dDf3PHtPoNm0K2HV-i_0-OQmQNa0yyCcwDH1KA0a3y-_64eg4c6cgbgrichB3CuJMdu4mZ53GfvgXhAEtgBv5Cw8ZW7w</recordid><startdate>20070501</startdate><enddate>20070501</enddate><creator>Westen, Peter</creator><general>Springer</general><scope>AAYXX</scope><scope>CITATION</scope><scope>8BJ</scope><scope>FQK</scope><scope>JBE</scope></search><sort><creationdate>20070501</creationdate><title>Two Rules of Legality in Criminal Law</title><author>Westen, Peter</author></sort><facets><frbrtype>5</frbrtype><frbrgroupid>cdi_FETCH-LOGICAL-c356t-ca4b6ef56b9c4fa9f3ec508ce154ca89e9fec2246eb7f6268dd7d13fc45360633</frbrgroupid><rsrctype>articles</rsrctype><prefilter>articles</prefilter><language>eng</language><creationdate>2007</creationdate><topic>Criminal justice</topic><topic>Criminal law</topic><topic>Criminal legislation</topic><topic>Criminal offenses</topic><topic>Criminality</topic><topic>Criminals</topic><topic>Defendants</topic><topic>Legal science</topic><topic>Legislation</topic><topic>Offenders</topic><topic>Philosophy of law</topic><topic>Punishment</topic><topic>Regulation</topic><topic>Rule of law</topic><topic>Statutory interpretation</topic><topic>Statutory law</topic><toplevel>peer_reviewed</toplevel><toplevel>online_resources</toplevel><creatorcontrib>Westen, Peter</creatorcontrib><collection>CrossRef</collection><collection>International Bibliography of the Social Sciences (IBSS)</collection><collection>International Bibliography of the Social Sciences</collection><collection>International Bibliography of the Social Sciences</collection><jtitle>Law and philosophy</jtitle></facets><delivery><delcategory>Remote Search Resource</delcategory><fulltext>fulltext</fulltext></delivery><addata><au>Westen, Peter</au><format>journal</format><genre>article</genre><ristype>JOUR</ristype><atitle>Two Rules of Legality in Criminal Law</atitle><jtitle>Law and philosophy</jtitle><date>2007-05-01</date><risdate>2007</risdate><volume>26</volume><issue>3</issue><spage>229</spage><epage>305</epage><pages>229-305</pages><issn>0167-5249</issn><eissn>1573-0522</eissn><abstract>Criminal law scholars approach legality in various ways. Some scholars eschew over-arching principles and proceed directly to one or more distinct "rules": (1) the rule against retroactive criminalization; (2) the rule that criminal statutes be construed narrowly; (3) the rule against the judicial creation of common-law offenses; and (4) the rule that vague criminal statutes are void. Other scholars seek a single principle, i.e., the "principal of legality," that they claim underlies the four rules. In contrast, I believe that both approaches are misguided. There is no such thing as a single "principle of legality;" yet, the four aforementioned rules are not unrelated to each other. The so-called "principle of legality" consists of two distinct norms that derive, respectively, from two fundamental principles of criminal justice, viz., the principle, "No person shall be punished in the absence of a bad mind," and the principle that underlies the maxim, "Every person is presumed innocent until proven guilty." The first norm of legality explains the rules regarding ex post facto legislation, and rules regarding "notice" and "fair warning" of judicial decisions. When a person is punished for violating a rule that was non-existent or unclear at the time he acted, he is punished for conduct that the state now condemns and seeks to prevent by means of penal sanctions. Accordingly, at the time the person is prosecuted, his claim is not that he did not do anything that the state regards as wrong, but, rather, that he neither knew nor should have known that he was doing something that the state would come to regard as wrong. He ought, indeed, to be excused for his mistake, but only because of a principle that is common to excuses generally: "No person ought to be punished in the absence of a guilty mind." He should be excused because even when a person does something the state condemns and seeks to prevent, he ought not to be blamed for it unless he was motivated in a certain way, namely, by an attitude of disrespect for the legitimate interests of the political community by whose norms he is bound. The Second norm of legality informs several of the remaining rules, though not all of them. The second norm is that a person ought not to be punished in the name of a political community unless it can confidently be said that the community officially regards his conduct as warranting the criminal punishment at issue. It is a norm that is most commonly associated with the rule of lenity, but it is not confined to the construction of statutes that are ambiguous or vague. It can also be also violated when a person is punished for violating a statute that has fallen into desuetude, regardless of how widely promulgated or narrowly defined the statute may be. This second norm derives from a principle that also underlies the presumption of innocence — the only difference being that the presumption of innocence is a preference for acquittal in the event of uncertainty regarding the facts which an actor is charged, while the second norm of legality is a preference for acquittal in the event of uncertainty regarding the scope of the offense which he is charged. Nevertheless, one "rule " remains that this analysis throws into question — namely, the rule that "vague" criminal statutes are void. Criminal statutes are sometimes so broadly defined that they do, indeed, infringe constitutionally protected rights of speech, movement, etc. — in which event they ought to be invalidated on those very grounds. And criminal statutes are sometimes so broadly drafted that, before applying them, courts ought to construe them to apply only to constitutionally unprotected acts that courts can confidently say the relevant political community regards as warranting punishment. But once statutes are so construed to apply only to constitutionally unprotected conduct, courts have no further reason to invalidate them because, with respect to the narrowly defined conduct such statutes are construed to prohibit, "common social duty" alone ought to alert actors that their conduct is suspect.</abstract><pub>Springer</pub><doi>10.1007/s10982-006-0007-7</doi><tpages>77</tpages></addata></record>
fulltext fulltext
identifier ISSN: 0167-5249
ispartof Law and philosophy, 2007-05, Vol.26 (3), p.229-305
issn 0167-5249
1573-0522
language eng
recordid cdi_proquest_miscellaneous_36662654
source International Bibliography of the Social Sciences (IBSS); JSTOR Archival Journals and Primary Sources Collection; Springer Link
subjects Criminal justice
Criminal law
Criminal legislation
Criminal offenses
Criminality
Criminals
Defendants
Legal science
Legislation
Offenders
Philosophy of law
Punishment
Regulation
Rule of law
Statutory interpretation
Statutory law
title Two Rules of Legality in Criminal Law
url http://sfxeu10.hosted.exlibrisgroup.com/loughborough?ctx_ver=Z39.88-2004&ctx_enc=info:ofi/enc:UTF-8&ctx_tim=2025-01-01T06%3A36%3A55IST&url_ver=Z39.88-2004&url_ctx_fmt=infofi/fmt:kev:mtx:ctx&rfr_id=info:sid/primo.exlibrisgroup.com:primo3-Article-jstor_proqu&rft_val_fmt=info:ofi/fmt:kev:mtx:journal&rft.genre=article&rft.atitle=Two%20Rules%20of%20Legality%20in%20Criminal%20Law&rft.jtitle=Law%20and%20philosophy&rft.au=Westen,%20Peter&rft.date=2007-05-01&rft.volume=26&rft.issue=3&rft.spage=229&rft.epage=305&rft.pages=229-305&rft.issn=0167-5249&rft.eissn=1573-0522&rft_id=info:doi/10.1007/s10982-006-0007-7&rft_dat=%3Cjstor_proqu%3E27652617%3C/jstor_proqu%3E%3Cgrp_id%3Ecdi_FETCH-LOGICAL-c356t-ca4b6ef56b9c4fa9f3ec508ce154ca89e9fec2246eb7f6268dd7d13fc45360633%3C/grp_id%3E%3Coa%3E%3C/oa%3E%3Curl%3E%3C/url%3E&rft_id=info:oai/&rft_pqid=36662654&rft_id=info:pmid/&rft_jstor_id=27652617&rfr_iscdi=true